In stable structures, there is a canonical ternary relation on subsets of the structure, interpreted as " is independent from over ." There is also a closely connected notion of a "non-forking extension" of a complete type. This is related to as follows: if and is a tuple, is a non-forking extension of if , and is a forking extension of if . This depends only on and . The non-forking extensions of a complete type can be thought of as the "generic" or "canonical" extensions, in a certain sense.
The ternary independence relation and the relation of non-forking can be defined through several different approaches, described below. In practice, what is more important than the definition is the formal properties possessed by these relations. In fact, these properties can be used to axiomatize . The manipulation of independence and non-forking via these axioms and other properties is called the forking calculus. Forking computations play a key role in many proofs in stability theory.
In superstable theories, forking is closely connected to ranks such as Lascar rank and Morley rank. In a general stable theory, these ranks may explode. Certain arguments that work in superstable settings can be generalized to stable theories through reformulation in terms of . The relation also appears in many of the basic definitions of stability theory, such as Lascar rank, stationary types, orthogonal types, regular types, domination, and weight.
Forking calculus in stable theories can be generalized to simple theories, and more generally, rosy theories. Along the way, one or two of the axioms must be dropped, however.
Work in a monster model of a stable theory . Recall that the strong type of over , denoted , is the type of over , the algebraic closure of in . In stable theories, strong types have canonical extensions: there is a unique complete type over which extends and which is -invariant. Denoting this unique extension by , one can make the following definition: if , then is a non-forking extension of if and only if It turns out that this definition depends only on and .
Then for , one defines to mean that for every finite , is a non-forking extension of .
See below for some alternative definitions.
Some of the above properties, such as symmetry, are more readily expressed in terms of independence, while others, such as transitivity, are more readily expressed in terms of non-forking extensions. Part of the complexity of forking calculus comes from the interplay of these two notions.
The above conditions actually characterize stable theories, in the following sense: if is a theory with monster model for which there exists a ternary relation satisfying the above axioms, then is stable and is forking independence.
Forking is closely related to ranks such as Morley rank and Lascar rank. If is one of Morley rank, Lascar rank, or Shelah infinity-rank, then governs forking, in the following sense: if is a type extending and , then
Equivalently, means that , and means that .
If has finite Lascar rank, can be defined very symmetrically as follows: means that for every finite tuple from and from ,
Aside from the axioms listed above, there are a number of other commonly used properties of forking:
There are a number of different approaches to defining non-forking and , aside from the one used above. All these definitions agree, for stable theories.
As a slight variant of the definition given above, one can proceed as follows. If and are finite, means that where denotes the product operation on global invariant types. Alternatively, means that for two -definable global types and . Either way, is then defined to mean that for every finite and . Then is a non-forking extension of if and only if .
Shelah's original definition of forking proceeds as follows. A formula is said to divide over a set if there exists a -indiscernible sequence of realizations of such that is inconsistent. A formula is said to fork over a set if it implies a finite disjunction of formulas (with parameters from ), such that each divides over . A type forks (divides) over if some formula in it forks (divides) over .
Then one defines to mean that doesn’t fork over for every finite tuple from . In a stable theory, it turns out that one can equivalently replace "forking" with "dividing" in this definition. Shelah’s definition of is somewhat convoluted, but turns out to be the right definition for use with unstable theories, such as simple theories, NIP theories, and NTP2 theories.
In Poizat’s Course in Model Theory a different definition of forking is given for stable theories, using the fundamental order. If is a complete type over a model, we say that a formula is "represented" in if for some . If and are two complete types over models, we say that if every formula represented in is also represented in . If is an extension of , then holds, for example. This defines a pre-order on the class of types over models; the quotient poset is called the fundamental order. If is a type over an arbitrary set , and is a model, then among the equivalence classes of extensions of to , there is a unique maximum in the fundamental order. This maximum is called the bound of ; it does not depend on . Now if and are two complete types, and is an extension of , then is a non-forking extension of if and only if and have the same bound. So means that for every finite tuple from , and have the same bound.
In totally transcendental theories, as noted above, is a non-forking extension of if and only if . This can be used to define non-forking, in a totally transcendental setting. The analogous fact for Lascar rank in superstable theories cannot really be used as a definition, because Lascar rank is (usually) defined in terms of .
In a general stable theory, there is still a way to define using ranks. If is a finite set of formulas, and is a finite partial type, the local -rank is defined to be the Cantor-Bendixson rank of the space of -types over which are consistent with . If is an arbitrary partial type, is defined to be the minimum of , for a finite subtype of . In a stable theory, always holds. If is a type extending (complete types over different sets), then it turns out that is a non-forking extension of if and only if for every finite set of formulas . ::: ::: :::