In stability theory and its generalizations, forking is a way of making precise the notion of "generic extensions" of types and of independence. A formula which forks over a set of parameters is thought of as being "non-generic." If
is a complete type over some set
, the non-forking extensions of
are those extensions which contain no formula forking over
; these are thought of as the "generic" extensions of
.
Forking is also related to a notion of independence: one says that tuples and
are independent over a set
if
does not fork over
. This turns out to be a useful notion in the setting of stable theories, and their generalizations. In stable and simple theories, one has in particular the machinery of the forking calculus.
Fix some complete theory , and let
be a monster model. If
is a small set of parameters and
is a formula with parameters from
, one says that
divides over
if there is a
-indiscernible sequence
of realizations of
such that
is inconsistent. Alternatively, without mentioning indiscernible sequences, one can define dividing as follows: a formula
is said to
-divide over
, for
a positive integer, if there is a sequence
of realizations of
such that
is
-inconsistent, that is, such that any
-element subset of
is inconsistent.
A formula is said to fork over
if it implies a finite disjunction of formulas (with parameters from
) each of which divides over
. That is, there is some
and
such that
Any formula which divides over
forks over
, though there are examples of the converse failing.
A partial type is said to fork over
(resp. divide over
) if it implies some formula which forks (resp. divides) over
. If
is a complete type over
, a non-forking extension of
is an extension which does not fork over
.
If is a tuple and
and
are small sets, one says that
is (forking) independent from
over
, written
, if
doesn't fork over
, i.e.,
is a non-forking extension of
. If
,
, and
are small sets, then
means that
for every finite tuple
from
. In general, this notion is not symmetric:
need not be equivalent to
. Simple theories are exactly the theories for which this symmetry always holds; they include stable theories.
In the theory of algebraically closed fields, forking turns out to be related to algebraic independence. If is an extension of fields (seen as substructures of the monster) and
is a finite tuple, then it turns out that
if and only if
.
Forking is defined to ensure that it has the following extension property: if , any partial type over
which does not fork over
can be extended to a complete type over
which does not fork over
. Dividing does not have this property. In fact, a partial type
can be extended to a global complete type which does not divide over
if and only if the original type
does not fork over
. A global type divides over
if and only if it forks over
.
Dividing can be defined more directly, in terms of indiscernible sequences. Specifically, the following are equivalent:
Forking has the following "left transitivity" property: if doesn't fork over
and
doesn't fork over
, then
doesn't fork over
. In terms of independence, this means that
and
together imply
. This is the mirror image of the more familiar kind of "right transitivity" which holds in simple theories: if
doesn't fork over
and
doesn't fork over
, then
doesn't fork over
. (In symbols:
and
imply
.)
TODO: monotonicity, base monotonicity, finite character, normality, "rigidity."
In general, any formula or type which divides over also forks over
. The converse need not hold. The standard example of this is the theory of a dense circular order. If one considers the structure with underlying set
and with a ternary predicate
interpreted as saying that
or
or
, then the formula
does not divide over
, but does fork over
. In complete detail, the formula
implies the disjunction of the two formulas
and
. All tuples
with
have the same type over
, and the sequence of formulas
is
-inconsistent. So forking is not the same as dividing in this theory.
On the other hand, it is known that forking and dividing agree in simple theories (including stable theories), o-minimal theories, and C-minimal theories (such as ACVF). Furthermore, in an NIP setting, it is proven by Chernikov and Kaplan that if is a model, then a formula forks over
if and only if it divides over
. That is, forking and dividing agree over models. This holds more generally in NTP
theories (again by Chernikov and Kaplan).
One useful consequence of forking=dividing (when it holds) is that no type forks over its base. That is, never forks over
. This comes from the easily verifiable fact that no formula over
can divide over
.
In simple theories, one has the full machinery of the forking calculus. Forking satisfies symmetry: is equivalent to
. This allows one to make definitions like Lascar rank, weight, independence, domination, and so on. Forking also satisfies local character: there is a cardinal
such that for every finite tuple
and set
, there is some subset
such that
and
. In other words, every type doesn't fork over some subtype of size bounded by
.
In NIP theories, non-forking has an equivalent description in terms of Lascar or compact (KP) strong types. As in any theory, doesn't fork over
if and only if
has an extension to a global type
which doesn't divide over
. In the NIP setting, however, it turns out that the following are equivalent for a global type
:
For stable theories, Lascar strong type, compact strong type, and strong type all agree, so one recovers the characterization of non-forking over as having an
-invariant global extension.
Main article: Forking in stable theories. ::: ::: :::