Let M be a structure. Definable closure and algebraic closure are two closure operators on M. If S is a subset of M, and a is an element (or finite tuple) from M, then
The definable closure of S is denoted dcl(S) and the algebraic closure is denoted acl(S). Sometimes we want dcl(S) and acl(S) to be subsets of M, in which case we take dcl(S) and acl(S) to be the sets of singletons in the definable closure and algebraic closure of S, respectively. There is not a very big distinction, because it turns out that a tuple a is in dcl(S) or acl(S) if and only if each coordinate of a is in dcl(S) or acl(S), respectively.
Both dcl(-) and acl(-) are finitary closure operators on M, meaning that
Also, in general one has dcl(S) ⊆ acl(S).
A set S is algebraically closed if S = acl(S), and definably closed if S = dcl(S).
Like most good concepts in model theory, these notions behave well under elementary extensions. Specifically, if is an elementary extension of M, and S ⊆ M, then dcl(S) computed inside N is the same as dcl(S) computed inside M. The same holds for acl(S).
If a ∈ acl(S), then a is in some finite S-definable set D. The intersection of all such D is still a finite S-definable set containing a, so there is a unique minimal finite S-definable set D containing a. The set D consists exactly of the realizations of tp(a/S). The elements of D are called the conjugates of a over S.
If M is |S|+-saturated, then
If furthermore M is |S|+-strongly homogeneous, then one gets a nice description of dcl(S) and acl(S) in terms of automorphisms:
ACF: Let K be an algebraically closed field, and S be a subset of K. Then
In particular, in characteristic zero, dcl(S) is just the field generated by S.
DLO: If M is a dense linear order, and S is a subset of M, then acl(S) = dcl(S) = S. In other words, all sets are algebraically closed and definably closed.
RCF: If K is a real closed field, and S is a subset of K, then acl(S) and dcl(S) are both equal to the relative algebraic closure in K of the field generated by S.
ACVF: If K is an algebraically closed valued field, non-trivially valued, and S is a subset of K, then
Linearly ordered structures: In general, if M is a structure with a 0-definable total ordering, then acl(-) and dcl(-) agree on M.
This section proves the unproven claims made above.
We asserted that a ∈ dcl(S) if and only if a = f(b) for some 0-definable function f and some tuple b from S.
Proof: If a ∈ dcl(S), then {a} is S-definable. So there is some formula and some tuple b from S such that
Let be the formula
In other words, asserts that not only does hold, but that no other value of x works.
Now holds. And for every tuple c from M, the set is either a singleton or empty. Therefore is the graph of (the transpose of) a 0-definable (partial) function f such that a = f(b).
(If we wanted a total definable function, we could set f(b) = b when f(b) is currently undefined, or something similar.) QED.
Lemma: An n-tuple a is in dcl(S) if and only if each coordinate of a is in dcl(S). Similarly, a is in acl(S) if and only if each coordinate of a is in acl(S).
As a consequence of this, the notions of algebraic and definable closure are determined by what they do to singletons. Proof: For 1 ≤ i ≤ n, let πi : Mn -> M be the projection onto the ith coordinate. Let ai be the ith coordinate of a.
Suppose first that a is in dcl(S). Then {a} is S-definable. So is πi({a}) = {ai} for each coordinate i. Consequently, ai is in the definable closure of S for each i. Conversely, if {ai} is S-definable for each i, then so is
,
so a is in dcl(S).
Next suppose that a is in acl(S). Thus a is in some finite S-definable set D ⊆ Mn. For each i, ai is in the finite S-definable set πi(D) so ai ∈ acl(S).
Conversely, suppose that ai ∈ acl(S) for each i. Then for each i there is an S-definable finite set Di ⊆ M containing ai. Then a is in a finite S-definable set:
so a ∈ acl(S). QED.
Finitariness: Suppose a is in dcl(S). Then {a} is S-definable. The definition can only use a finite subset S0 ⊆ S. So {a} is S0-definable, so a ∈ dcl(S0). Similarly, if a is in acl(S), then a is in some finite S-definable set D. But the definition of D can only use finitely many elements of S, so D is S0-definable for some S0. Then a ∈ acl(S0).
Increasingness: Suppose a ∈ S. Then the set {a} is S-definable, by the formula x = a. So a ∈ dcl(S). And {a} is finite, so a ∈ acl(S). Therefore S ⊆ dcl(S) and S ⊆ acl(S).
Monotonicity: Suppose S ⊆ T. If a ∈ dcl(S), then {a} is S-definable, hence T-definable, and a ∈ dcl(T). Similarly, if a ∈ acl(S), then a is in a finite S-definable set D. Of course D is T-definable, so a ∈ acl(T). Thus dcl(S) ⊆ dcl(T) and acl(S) ⊆ acl(T).
Idempotence of dcl(-): As dcl(-) is increasing, we have dcl(S) ⊆ dcl(dcl(S)). We need to show the reverse inclusion. Suppose a ∈ dcl(dcl(S)). Then for some tuple b from dcl(S) and some formula . By the Lemma above, b ∈ dcl(S). Consequently, for some tuple c from S and some formula .
Let assert that there is a unique y such that holds and that for this y, holds as well, so is the formula:
Then holds. Also, if holds for some tuple a' then holds, and consequently a' = a. So . But is 0-definable, and c is a tuple from S, so a ∈ dcl(S). Consequently, dcl(dcl(S)) ⊆ dcl(S).
Idempotence of acl(-): This one is hardest. Because acl(-) is increasing, we have acl(S) ⊆ acl(acl(S)). We need the reverse inclusion. Suppose that a ∈ acl(acl(S)). Then a is in a finite acl(S)-definable set D. Write where b ∈ acl(S). If k is the cardinality of D, we can modify the formula so that for every value of y, at most k values of x satisfy . Specifically, we replace with the formula
Similarly, since b ∈ acl(S), we can find a formula , a number j, and a tuple c from S such that holds, and such that for every value of z, at most j values of y satisfy .
Now let be the formula
For each value of z, there at at most kj values of x satisfying . So . But , so a ∈ acl(S), because c is from S.
If is an elementary extension of M, and S ⊆ M, then dcl(S) is the same when computed in N or M. The same holds for acl(S).
Proof: Both of these claims follow easily from the fact that if is finite, then , a general fact about elementary extensions. From the definition of elementary extension, one knows that
However, we can write a statement asserting that there are exactly values of x such that holds. Then , and hence . Thus . Two finite sets of the same size must be equal, if one includes the other. QED.
Suppose a ∈ acl(S), and D is the set of conjugates of a over S. Then D is exactly the set of realizations of tp(a/S).
Proof: Suppose b realizes tp(a/S). The type tp(a/S) includes the statement that x ∈ D, so b ∈ D. Conversely, suppose b ∈ D, but b does not realize tp(a/S). Then there is some S-definable set E containing a but not b. Then D ∩ E is a finite S-definable set containing a. By choice of D, D = D ∩ E, so D ⊆ E. But b ∈ D and b is not in E, a contradiction. QED.
Claim: Suppose M is |S|+-saturated, and a is a finite tuple. Then a ∈ dcl(S) if and only if tp(a/S) has a unique realization in M.
Proof: If a ∈ dcl(S), then D := {a} is S-definable. The type of a over S includes the statement that x ∈ D. Consequently, any other realization of tp(a/S) must be in D, i.e., must equal a.
Conversely, suppose a is the unique realization of tp(a/S). Let p(x) be the partial type over S ∪ {a} consisting of tp(a/S) together with the statement x ≠ a. By assumption, there are no realizations of p(x) in M. By the saturation of M, it follows that p(x) must be inconsistent, i.e., not finitely satisfiable. So there is some formula such that
or equivalently
,
so . Since we know that . Thus . Since b is a tuple from S, we conclude that a ∈ dcl(S). QED.
Claim: Suppose M is |S|+-saturated, and a is a finite tuple. Then a ∈ acl(S) if and only if tp(a/S) has finitely many realizations.
Proof: If a ∈ acl(S), then a is in a finite S-definable set D. The type of a over S includes the statement that x ∈ D. So any realization of tp(a/S) must be in D. Therefore tp(a/S) has finitely many realizations.
Conversely, suppose that tp(a/S) has finitely many realizations b1, ..., bn. Let p(x) be the partial type over S ∪ {b1, ..., bn} asserting that x satisfies tp(a/S) and x does not equal any bi. By assumption, p(x) is not realized in M. By saturation, p(x) must be inconsistent. It follows that there is some formula such that
or equivalently
So is finite. As , we know that . Therefore a is in a finite S-definable set, and consequently a ∈ acl(S). QED.
Claim: Suppose that M is |S|+-saturated and |S|+-strongly homogeneous. Then a ∈ dcl(S) if and only if a is fixed by Aut(M/S), and a ∈ acl(S) if and only if a has a finite orbit under Aut(M/S).
Proof: By strong homogeneity, the orbit of a under Aut(M/S) is exactly the set of realizations of tp(a/S). Now use the previous claims. QED. ::: ::: :::