Two tuples and
(in the same sort) have the same strong type over a set of parameters
if
holds for every
-definable equivalence relation with finitely many equivalence classes. An equivalent condition is that
and
have the same type over
, the set of imaginaries which are algebraic over
.
If and
have the same strong type over
, then they have the same type over
, so this is a "stronger" notion than the notion of a type. The strong type of
over
is sometimes denoted
. The set of realizations of
is type-definable, and so can be thought of as a partial type over some set.
There are two even stronger notions of "strong type" which appear in certain settings.
Two tuples and
have the same Kim-Pillay strong type over
if
holds for every equivalence relation
which is type-definable over
and has a bounded number of equivalence classes. Here, "bounded" means that the number of equivalence classes does not grow in elementary extensions, or is small compared to the size of the monster. The equivalence relation of having the same Kim-Pillay strong type is the unique smallest bounded equivalence relation which is type-definable over
.
As in the case of strong type, the set of realizations of the Kim-Pillay strong type of over
is type-definable, and so a Kim-Pillay strong type can be thought of as a partial type over some set. In the same way that strong type can be defined more directly using imaginaries, Kim-Pillay strong type can be defined more directly using hyperimaginaries:
and
have the same Kim-Pillay strong type over
if and only if they have the same type over
, the set of hyperimaginaries which have bounded number of conjugates over
.
Finally, the relation of having the same Lascar strong type over is defined to be the minimum
-invariant equivalence relation with a bounded number of classes. There are several equivalent definitions:
A theory is called -compact if the relation of having the same Lascar strong type over
is type-definable for every
. Equivalently, Kim-Pillay type and Lascar strong type agree. Simple theories are known to be
-compact.
For stable theories, something even better happens: strong type, Kim-Pillay strong type, and Lascar strong type all agree. This also happens for o-minimal and c-minimal theories, by a result in Hrushovski and Pillay’s paper On NIP and Invariant Measures.
Let be the ambient monster model.
The two definitions of strong type are equivalent.
Proof. Suppose that holds for every
-definable equivalence relation with finitely many equivalence classes. To show that
, it suffices to show that for every
-definable set
,
. But if
is
-definable, then the code for
is in
, hence has finitely many conjugates over
. Let
be the equivalence relation such that
if and only if
for every conjugate
of
over
. If
has
conjugates over
, then
has at most
equivalence classes. The equivalence classes of
are boolean combinations of definable sets, so
is definable. Since
is clearly
-invariant,
is
-definable. Hence
holds. Therefore
.
Conversely, suppose and
have the same type over
. Let
be a
-definable equivalence relation with finitely many equivalence classes. If
is an equivalence class of
and
, then
is an equivalence class of
. Since
has finitely many classes, there are finitely many possibilities for
, so the code for
is in
. Therefore,
is
-definable, and
. As
was an arbitrary equivalence class of
, it follows that
. QED
If and
have the same strong type over
, then they have the same type over
.
Proof. If is a
-definable set, then we need to show that
. Let
be the equivalence relation with two classes,
and the complement of
. Then
is
-definable with finitely many classes, so
. QED
There is a minimum equivalence relation which is type-definable over
and has a bounded number of equivalence classes. (So the definition of Kim-Pillay strong type makes sense.)
Proof. If is a small family of equivalence relations which are type-definable over
, then
is also an equivalence relation which is type-definable over
. Moreover, if each
is bounded (i.e., has a bounded number of equivalence classes), then so is the equivalence relation
. Take
to be the class of all bounded equivalence relations which are type-definable over
. QED
Similarly, one proves that there is a minimum equivalence relation which is bounded and
-invariant. (If
is
-invariant, then whether
holds depends only on
. There are a bounded number of possibilities for
, so there are a bounded number of
-invariant equivalence relations.)
Fix . Let
mean that there is some model
such that
. Let
indicate that there is some
-indiscernible sequence beginning with
. Then
and
have the same transitive closure.
Proof. Suppose that holds. Then
holds for some model
containing
. Let
be a global M-invariant type extending
. Let
be a Morley sequence for
over
, so
,
,
, and so on. Then
and
are both indiscernible sequences over
. So
and
. So
is in the transitive closure of
. (Technically speaking, we should also show that
is symmetric. This follows from the fact that if
is an indiscernible sequence, then we can extend this sequence to the left, reverse it, and throw away the terms preceding
.)
Conversely, suppose that holds. Then there is a
-indiscernible sequence
whose first two terms are
and
. Let
be a model containing
. Let
be an
-indiscernible sequence extracted from
. Then
and
have the same type over
, so we can find some
such that
. As
,
is a model containing
. As
and
is
-indiscernible,
is
-indiscernible. Thus all elements of
have the same type over
. In particular,
. So
. QED
The transitive closure of is a bounded equivalence relation.
Proof. Let be some model containing
. Then any two elements having the same type over
are equivalent with respect to the transitive closure of
. So the transitive closure of
has no more equivalence classes than there are types over
. QED
If is a
-invariant bounded equivalence relation, and
, then
.
Proof. By definition of , we can find some
-indiscernible sequence
such that
and
. Extend the sequence to be longer than the number of equivalence classes of
. Suppose
doesn’t hold. By
-indiscernibility of the sequence, and
-invariance of
, we see that
fails to hold for any
. So each element of the indiscernible sequence is in a different equivalence class, contradicting the choice of the length of the indiscernible sequence. QED
So the transitive closure of is contained in any
-invariant bounded equivalence relation, and is therefore the unique minimum
-invariant bounded equivalence relation. Consequently, the transitive closure of
agrees with the transitive closure of
agrees with unique minimum
-invariant bounded equivalence relation. So the definitions of Lascar strong type given above agree.
... ::: ::: :::